In part 1 of this series of my reflections on James Q. Wilson's book The Moral Sense, I summarized the book's main aims and shared a few of the most salient points that I found of conceptual and practical value. In this post, I begin to tackle the book's second section, which examines four key moral sentiments: sympathy, fairness, self-control, and duty. Specifically I focus on sympathy.
As preparation for a review of moral senses such as sympathy, it may be helpful to recall what Prof. Wilson is and is not doing by exploring these sentiments:
I am not trying to discover "facts" that will prove "values"; I am endeavoring to uncover the evolutionary, developmental, and cultural origins of our moral habits and our moral sense. But in discovering these origins, I suspect that we will encounter uniformities; and by revealing uniformities, I think that we can better appreciate what is general, nonarbitrary, and emotionally compelling about human nature. (26)
In the chapters on the four moral sentiments, Prof. Wilson does just this. He weaves together the evolutionary, developmental, and cultural origins of these respective moral habits and senses. In doing so, I find his descriptive observations -- which are helpful in their own right as an organizing heuristic for thinking about moral matters -- to pull me toward practical considerations and action.
I offered a few remarks on sympathy, "the human capacity for being affected by the feelings and experiences of others" (30), in the earlier post. It helped to exemplify the basic approach to the subject that Prof. Wilson takes. Sympathy, like the other sentiments, functions in human life as both a motivation for moral action and a standard for it. A few other brief notes are worth mentioning.
I offered a few remarks on sympathy, "the human capacity for being affected by the feelings and experiences of others" (30), in the earlier post. It helped to exemplify the basic approach to the subject that Prof. Wilson takes. Sympathy, like the other sentiments, functions in human life as both a motivation for moral action and a standard for it. A few other brief notes are worth mentioning.
In all of his chapters on the sentiments, if to varying extents, Mr. Wilson explores the relevance of evolutionary biology on the moral sense in view. The theory of inclusive fitness, advanced by William Hamilton after Charles Darwin, fills out the latter's theory of a species' successful self-propagation over time: "An individual is reproductively successful to the extent that his genes occur in the next generation, and he can assure that occurrence not only by reproducing himself but also by assisting in the reproduction of individuals who have his genes" (41).
Professor Wilson admits that this theory might explain why we humans sacrifice ourselves for our kin, but it does not go very far in explaining why we humans are willing to sacrifice ourselves for our grandmother, who is past childbearing age and cannot deposit genes to future generations. It also does not explain why we may rush into a burning building to save a dog or adopted children, with whom we have no genetic similarity (42).
Maybe the notion of reciprocal altruism can help: "we engage in altruistic acts -- such as helping nonrelatives, caring for adopted children, or being affectionate toward pets -- in order to impress others with our dependability and hence to increase our opportunities to have profitable exchanges with these others" (43). Mr. Wilson points out that as an explanation this utilitarian idea has truth elements to commend it, but a more basic motivation -- "a prior, dominant fact" (44) -- must be recognized. We more basically value reciprocity in human relationships to which we are naturally drawn because we fear isolation and loneliness and we value human sociable companionship. This human trait governs the theory of altruism, and it is at the heart of sympathy.
What can be said about evolution and sympathy, then, is this: "If sympathy is widespread, it must have been adaptive, but what was selected for is a generalized trait that both encourages reproductive fitness and stimulates sympathetic behavior. That trait, or adaptive mechanism, is attachment or affiliative behavior" (44; emphasis original).
We are naturally more sympathetic to those to whom we are most similar. Humans naturally think of themselves first in terms of a small group (a nuclear family, an extended kinship, a local community, religious group), but we can imagine ourselves as part of a larger sphere and, with extra effort, behave sympathetically toward those who differ from us in race, religion, and culture. Earlier, Prof. Wilson makes the keen insight that "life-styles" today is the nonjudgmental word for what used to be called "character," and I might broaden that to say "culture" (7). This is a point that illumines the linguistic shift which has occurred in morality and permissible moral discourse, on the one hand, and that, on the other, contemporizes the tendency toward small group affiliation, toward those who live life as we do.
Two towering moral philosophers, both Scotsmen, in their own way identified sympathy as either the source of moral sentiments (Adam Smith) or at least as one of the two extremely powerful and basic sources along with utility (David Hume). Both men viewed moral philosophy as inextricably linked to the study of human nature. The place of sympathy in the thought of other philosophers could be mentioned, but the central place of it in Smith's and Hume's writings should prompt us to reflect more than we typically do -- or I have done -- on what it is, how it is manifested, and how it might be cultivated.
Sympathy can lead to benevolent feelings and actions, Mr. Wilson notes, but we should not limit sympathy to the rosier side of life:
Sympathy is often expressed by phrases that convey not tenderness or concern, but anger and vengeance. If we see an abominable act -- say a man laughing while torturing an innocent baby -- our first reaction is not likely to be an expression of sympathy for the child but rage at its tormenter; and this will be true even if it is not our child. Sympathy is often wrongly portrayed as entirely a tender sentiment: sympathetic people are sometimes described as soft, warm, or weepy. They often are; but they are much more than that, and some of the most sympathetic people have no trace of cuddliness in their temperament. Even so staunch a utilitarian as John Stuart Mill recognized this: "It is natural to resent and to repel or to retaliate any harm done or attempted against ourselves or against those with whom we sympathize." (40)
If we do not limit sympathy to the soft and warm side of life, then we should perhaps also be prepared to view anger and vengeance as legitimate moral responses that stem from not just a sense of justice but also of sympathy.
In this way, we may also have stumbled upon an important observation: moral senses such as sympathy and justice are connected. We may not be able to say (yet) with someone like Adam Smith that sympathy is the primary cause of moral sensibility. But we recognize that there is interplay between the moral senses.
Moreover, if there is any truth to the commonplace that men and women are different (a truism to which some do in fact object), and if on the whole it is the case that women naturally display the tender and sensitive side of sympathy more than do men, then men would do well to remind themselves that such sympathy may be a manifestation of moral sense. And it may be a commendable moral expression just as much as the stereotypical male tendency to display the more violent and vengeful side of sympathy.
To be sure, members of each sex can and often do display the moral trait that I have associated as more typical of the other. The point is not gender stereotypes per se but better mutual appreciation among the sexes. Professor Wilson's discussion of sympathy, which recognizes its pluriformity, provides men and women enhanced grounds for doing what they already know that they ought to do: live patiently in an understanding way with one another. Sympathy has come full circle.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Brief comments to this post are welcome; however, please respect the civil tone of conversation that I wish to cultivate in this forum.