- what is legal is not always just;
- what is permitted is not always prudent; and
- what is required is not always right.
Thursday, June 28, 2012
Reminders
Big picture reminders are sometimes necessary. For instance:
Labels:
convention,
culture,
government,
health care,
justice,
law,
liberty,
morality,
power,
prudence,
state
Wednesday, June 27, 2012
A tad more than a $6,300 fine
This article in today's The New York Times about a Chinese woman's pregnancy and the government's decision to execute her child touches on some topics I raised in previous posts this month (first here and then here).
Labels:
abortion,
family,
government,
health care,
justice,
state
Friday, June 15, 2012
Enduring Classical Benefits
In a recent post, I drew attention to a political and ethical tension: the government's position in the United States to permit gendercide (or female foeticide), which is legal, and the ostensible position of the United States government with respect to other countries regarding the same permitted termination of life, which the Secretary of State has said should be prohibited.
Shortly after making that blog entry, I ran across the following discussion of ethical matters in ancient Greece. It has to do with the development of moral theory and practice from Homeric myth to fifth-century Athens. In his A Short History of Ethics, Alasdair MacIntyre discusses the tug of war between nomos (law, custom, convention) and physis (nature), the order of society and the order of the universe, as it relates to one's understanding of virtue and moral expressions within cultures and across them. I take it that this tug of war is parallel to the tension in the U.S. domestic approach to gendercide through selective abortion and its foreign approach to the same question.
I offer the following, then, as evidence of the enduring benefits of a classical education. The tension in the U.S. is not new. The Athenians, too, were conflicted. Who knew, right, that an account of the development of moral reasoning in ancient Greece could be, well, just so relevant to contemporary discussions? It is. What, then, might we learn about justice from their experience and moral investigations that can help to improve ours?
Between Homer and writers five centuries later there is a great change in Greek myths about the order of the universe. The Homeric myth does reflect, though with much distortion, the workings of an actual society in which a close form of functional organization is presupposed by the moral and evaluative forms of appraisal which are in use. The later assertions of order in the universe reflect not a structure that is, but one that was, or one that is struggling to survive. They are conservative protests against the disintegration of the older forms and the transition to the city-state. The myths themselves cannot but open up the question of the difference between the order of the universe and the order of society. But above all, this question is sharpened by a widening awareness of radically different social orders.
The impact of the Persian invasions, of colonization, of increase in trade and therefore in travel, all these brings home the fact of different cultures. The result is that the distinction between what holds good in Egypt but not in Persia, or in Athens but not in Megara, on the one hand, and what is the case universally as part of the order of things becomes overwhelmingly important. The question asked about any moral rule or social practice is, Is it part of the essentially local realm of nomos (convention, custom) or of the essentially universal realm of physis (nature)? Linked to this is of course the question, Is it open to me to choose what rules I shall make my own or what restraints I shall observe (as it may be open to me to choose which city I shall live in and what therefore shall be the nomos by which I live)? or does the nature of the universe set limits upon what I may legitimately choose? (MacIntyre, Short History, 10-11)
… Different cities observe different customs and different laws. Does and should justice differ from city to city? Does justice hold only within a given community between citizens? or should it hold also between cities? The Athenians condemn the character of Alcibiades because he did not observe the restraints of dikaiosune in his behavior within the Athenian state. But their own envoys behave just like Alcibiades in their attitude toward other states. That is, they equate what is morally permissible with what the agent has the power to do. (MacIntyre, Short History, 11-12)
Labels:
Alasdair MacIntyre,
convention,
culture,
education,
government,
Homer,
justice,
law,
morality,
power,
state,
virtue
Monday, June 11, 2012
Initiative in the Poverty Debate
These days, questions about justice, particularly that nebulous but ubiquitous term social justice, turn in my hearing mostly on the basic structure of life in the United States. It is a structure, it is claimed, that in its very fabric is unjust. Therefore, the unjust social fabric ineluctably results in inherently unequal opportunities, not to mention also unequal outcomes. A case in point, frequently offered as Exhibit A, is poverty.
Without discussing now the philosophical postulates about justice that this prevailing view reflects, I was struck by a report of Congressional testimony that was given last week on the subject of poverty. The Wall Street Journal reproduces in today's edition the following remarks by Ron Haskins of the Brookings Institution. (The Brookings Institution is generally considered a center-left think tank in Washington, D.C.) Mr. Haskins's point: certain behavior is an extremely accurate predictor of adult poverty or, alternately, general economic success.
Whatever one may think of Mr. Haskins's view, the Census data that he provides must be part of the ongoing political, economic, and moral debate. (The full transcript of his Senate testimony may be found here.)
Brookings Institution Senior Fellow Ron Haskins testifying before the Senate Finance Committee, June 5:I want to emphasize the importance of individual initiative in reducing poverty and promoting economic success. Young people can virtually assure that they and their families will avoid poverty if they follow three elementary rules for success—complete at least a high school education, work full time, and wait until age 21 and get married before having a baby. Based on an analysis of Census data, people who followed all three of these rules had only a 2% chance of being in poverty and a 72% chance of joining the middle class (defined as above $55,000 in 2010). These numbers were almost precisely reversed for people who violated all three rules, elevating their chance of being poor to 77% and reducing their chance of making the middle class to 4%.Individual effort and good decisions about the big events in life are more important than government programs. Call it blaming the victim if you like, but decisions made by individuals are paramount in the fight to reduce poverty and increase opportunity in America. The nation's struggle to expand opportunity will continue to be an uphill battle if young people do not learn to make better decisions about their future.A version of this article appeared June 11, 2012, on page A13 in the U.S. edition of The Wall Street Journal, with the headline: Notable & Quotable.
Friday, June 8, 2012
Contemporary Moral Dieting
David Brooks has a good column in today's The New York Times: "The Moral Diet."
In it, he discusses key points in a new book by Dan Ariely, The (Honest) Truth About Dishonesty.
(For those with online user access, Mr. Ariely is also interviewed by The Wall Street Journal in this 20-minute video, posted last night. The Duke University professor also penned this May 26 essay, "Why We Lie," in The Wall Street Journal.)
Mr. Brooks finds fascinating the presently prevailing Good Person Construct, which is a shift from moral conceptions that prevailed in the past:
(For those with online user access, Mr. Ariely is also interviewed by The Wall Street Journal in this 20-minute video, posted last night. The Duke University professor also penned this May 26 essay, "Why We Lie," in The Wall Street Journal.)
Mr. Brooks finds fascinating the presently prevailing Good Person Construct, which is a shift from moral conceptions that prevailed in the past:
But these days, people are more likely to believe in their essential goodness. People who live by the Good Person Construct try to balance their virtuous self-image with their selfish desires. They try to manage the moral plusses and minuses and keep their overall record in positive territory. In this construct, moral life is more like dieting: I give myself permission to have a few cookies because I had salads for lunch and dinner. I give myself permission to cheat a little because, when I look at my overall life, I see that I’m still a good person.The Good Person isn’t shooting for perfection any more than most dieters are following their diet 100 percent. It’s enough to be workably suboptimal, a tolerant, harmless sinner and a generally good guy.
Obviously, though, there’s a measurement problem. ...
As we go about doing our Good Person moral calculations, it might be worth asking: Is this good enough? Is this life of minor transgressions refreshingly realistic, given our natures, or is it settling for mediocrity?
There is a measurement problem, and successful pursuit of virtue, I too fear, indeed is now defined by mediocrity.
But there is also perhaps another problem. Is this moral pursuit to be conducted within the limits of individual human effort alone?
Mr. Brooks discusses Mr. Ariely's book in terms that may be true to the author's approach. I have not read the book, so I cannot say. But the language pervasive in the column about moral pursuit, and the Good Person Construct in particular, is decidedly individualistic. It is about "moral self-image," what I do on my moral diet. It is not about forces or agents outside of me that, in concert with me, are critical to solving the measurement problem, or the mediocrity problem, or the "good enough" question.
Maybe we need perspective and help from outside of ourselves to find our real moral selves -- and rightly to appraise what moral rectitude actually is.
Friday, June 1, 2012
Safe, Legal, and Targeted
Is it morally permissible to terminate a human life based upon that life-holder's sex (male or female) as long as the decision to terminate is free rather than forced?
This is essentially the question that was voted on in the U.S. House of Representatives yesterday. Technically, the question was the legality, not the morality, but never mind since those are confused in promulgating legislation that is supposed to reflect society's sense of justice, or what is right, which is to say what is moral. Congress took up the question of selective abortion -- i.e., the termination of the life -- of a healthy and developing human fetus based on sex, especially if the baby is female.
The answer that Congress gave in its procedural way was yes. Freedom of one's individual will is so important, evidently, that it allows one legally to discriminate lethally against another. Free termination of a life based upon sex discrimination is legally permissible. The message of the government, then, is that it is morally acceptable in the United States.
Perhaps reflecting home country bias, forced and frequently selective termination as practiced, for example, in China and India, is, however, not acceptable -- in fact it is condemnable -- according to U.S. standards. This practice in China and India is commonly called gendercide, or female foeticide.
The definition includes the deliberate determination to commit the killing act.
Whether one party is forced or free, a deliberate determination to kill an innocent is
made.
Secretary of State Hillary R. Clinton has said that this termination of a female life based on the fact that the child is female should be stopped:
Obviously, there’s work to be done in both India and China, because the infanticide rate of girl babies is still overwhelmingly high, and unfortunately with technology, parents are able to use sonograms to determine the sex of a baby, and to abort girl children simply because they’d rather have a boy.
So has the typically ineffective United Nations.
This raises a number of moral questions that relate to very practical considerations of wisdom:
- Should one's individual freedom of decision be held in such high esteem that the state entrenches lethal sexual discrimination of females?
- Could one legitimately call these targeted killings?
- Why is the practice in one country acceptable but not in another?
- What is the real "war on women"?
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)